As I've observed before, talk of reparations has been pretty scarce of late, but I'm wondering if it's going to make a comeback in the academy. For instance, last spring North Carolina came close to providing compensation to sterilization victims. And I now see that Andrew Valls at Oregon State has posted a new paper, "Liberal Egalitarianism and Black Reparations." Here is Valls' abstract:
Racial injustice in the United States has many manifestations, but the most tangible among them is material inequality. The racial gap, as measured by any indicator of wellbeing, is large and has changed little in recent decades. Since the civil rights era, the ratios of white to black household income and wealth have been remarkably consistent. Median black household income has hovered at around 60% of median white household income (Isaacs 2007). The wealth gap is much greater: before the Great Recession of 2007-09, the ratio of white to black household wealth stood at about ten to one; after the recession, it rose to astounding twenty to one (Kochlar, Fry, and Taylor 2011). Black unemployment has been roughly double that of whites for decades (Bureau of Labor Statistics 2011). The black poverty rate has been two to three times that of whites over the same period (DeNavas-Walt, Proctor, and Smith 2011).
These grim statistics have deep historical roots. Though the causes and mechanisms of ongoing racial inequality are complex, there is no doubt that much of the underlying cause of structural racial inequality in the United States is caused by patterns of segregation and practices of discrimination that have taken place for much of our history. The evidence of the roots of present-day racial inequality in historical practices, many of which had the active support or at least the acquiescence of governments at the federal, state, and local levels, is overwhelming (see Conley 1999; Massey and Denton 1993; Oliver and Shapiro 2006). The racialized character of inequality in the United States reflects the failure to confront and address the accumulated effects of the subordination and oppression of African Americans under slavery and Jim Crow, so racial inequality in the United States is a case of unrectified historic injustice.
This is the situation that some activists and scholars attempt to highlight by raising the issue of black reparations. The idea of black reparations is that the injustices of the past and their impact on the present provide powerful grounds for addressing racial inequality in public policy. Yet others, even some who support policies to reduce racial inequality, find the language of reparations unhelpful, or downright counterproductive. In this chapter I argue black reparations are demanded by justice, but that to appreciate the case for reparations requires putting it in its proper theoretical context.
North Carolina's proposed compensation is to actual victims, not to all people who generally kinda sorta look like victims who lived 200 years ago. Is this difference really that hard to comprehend? Paying the actual victim for the actual harm is not the same as taking the money from innocent children of Chinese, Mexican, Indian, Irish, Italian etc. immigrants to pay, say, Obama because Obama kinda looks like southern slaves, and the prospective payors do not.
Posted by: tired of this | October 01, 2012 at 03:22 PM
I didn't think he was saying that the North Carolina situation was the same as reparations for slavery. I took it to be a statement that the concept of making corrections for past wrongs -- indeed calling them "wrongs" -- is back in the news. The paper he refers to suggests that the "wrongs" of slavery are still doing their work.
Posted by: AGR | October 02, 2012 at 02:37 PM